What kind of philosopher was immanuel kant




















That is why it is impossible for us to understand something that is at the same time object and purpose. In such a case, there would be no distinction between perceiving a thing, understanding a thing, and the thing existing.

This is as close as our finite minds can get to understanding the mind of God. However, in dealing with the limited role discussed above, there is an implicit danger. If reason does not pay sufficient critical attention to the reflection involved the result is an antinomy sect. There could only be an antinomy if both principles were understood to be so constitutive. Kant, however, continues for several sections the discussion of the antinomy and its solution, in the end proposing a remarkable new solution.

In our understanding of the world and for any other understanding we could imagine the workings of , the universal principle law of nature never fully determines any particular thing in all its real detail. Thus these details, although necessary in themselves as part of the order of nature, must be contingent with respect to our universal concept. It is simply beyond our understanding that there should be a concept that, in itself, determines as necessary all the features of any particular thing.

As Kant explains it, an object so understood would be a whole that conditions all its parts. But a living organism would be just such a whole. As we have seen, to understand its possibility we have to apply through reflective judgment the rational idea of an intrinsic purpose. Here, as we have just seen, the problem of the contingency with respect to natural law is exacerbated.

But this idea is of a presentation of such a whole, and the presentation is conceived of as a purpose which conditions or leads to the production of the parts. This peculiarity of our understanding poses the possibility of another form of intelligence, the intellectus archetypus , an intelligence which is not limited to this detour of presentations in its thinking and acting. Such an understanding would not function in a world of appearances, but directly in the world of things-in-themselves.

Its power of giving the universal concepts and ideas would not be a separate power from its power of forming intuitions of particular things; concept and thing, thought and reality would be one. From the point of view of such an understanding, what we humans must conceive as the contingency of natural purposes with respect to the universal concept, is only an appearance.

For the intellectus archetypus , such natural purposes would indeed be necessary, in the same sense as events subject to mechanical natural law. Thus, the notion of an intellectus archetypus — and the corresponding distinction for us between appearances and things-in-themselves — gives Kant a more complete way of solving the above antinomy.

Because of the limitation of our understanding, we are incapable of knowing the details of the necessity of all natural processes. The idea of a natural purpose is an essential additional principle which partly corrects for this limitation, but also produces the antinomy. But the contingency introduced by the new principle is or, rather, may be only a contingency for us as intellectus ectypus , and therefore the principle of natural purposes does not contradict the demand of reason for necessity.

But it is above all important to remember that, at this point, Kant is not claiming that there is, or must be, or that he can prove there to be, such a being. But, in fact, Kant believes this to be an extraordinarily weak argument see for example sect. Kant, however, thinks he has an argument which is related to it, and which within certain limits works much better.

Overview: The notion of the intellectus archetypus is clearly heading in the direction of philosophical theology. In the Critique of Pure Reason , he provides some of the standard attacks on the cosmological and especially the ontological arguments. And in the Critique of Judgment , he argues that the argument from design, at least as normally stated, is very weak.

But he then asks whether practical reason — i. However, Kant claims that the moral law obligates us to consider the final purpose or aim of all moral action. This means the greatest possible happiness for all moral beings. Importantly, this goal is not the ground of morality — unlike ordinary instances of desire or action, wherein I act precisely because I want to reach the goal. Moral action is grounded in duty — but, subsequently, so to speak, we must be assured that the final purpose is actually possible.

Just as moral action must be possible through freedom, so the summum bonum must be possible through moral action. But the possibility of the summum bonum as the final purpose in nature appears to be questionable. Therefore, if our moral action is to make sense, there must be someone working behind the scenes. Moral action, therefore, assumes the existence of a God. After an extended discussion of the ins and outs of the role of teleological judgments in science, from sect.

Ultimately, again, these might be seen as part of the intention or design of the intelligent cause of creation. This, Kant says, is a perfectly understandable way of speaking sometimes, and even helps us to cognize certain natural processes, but has no objective foundation in science. There is always another way of looking at things for which what we thought was a purpose is in fact only a means to something else entirely e.

Nature per se does not, then, contain or pursue any such purposes, not even for man. But Kant is not quite yet finished with these kinds of problems, and introduces in sect. This is no longer an extrinsic purpose that nature might have. Still, it is clear that, again, there can be no intrinsic final purpose in nature -all natural products and events are conditioned, including the world around us, our own bodies and even our mental life.

And living beings, qua natural purposes, are conditioned by themselves. So, what kind of thing would such a final purpose be? As we have discovered on several previous occasions, for Kant human beings are not merely natural beings. As Kant emphasizes on several occasions — e. Because these are one and all reflective judgments, they entail neither a theoretical nor a practical conclusion as to what might be behind these purposes. But, Kant asks, is there any reason requiring us to assume nature is purposive with respect to practical reason?

Acting from the mere pure and universal form of the moral law is everything, the consequences of action do not enter into the equation. However, as Kant makes clear in the Introduction to the Critique of Judgment , the practical faculties in general have to do with desire — i. Kant claims that the moral law necessarily obligates us to consider the final purpose of moral action. However, it is not to be considered as the ground of morality, as would normally be the case in desire, when the presentation of the result my aim causes the action action leading to that aim.

Conceived of as a state of natural beings, this means the greatest possible happiness for all moral beings. Kant is using this inter-implication of moral law and final purpose of moral action as a premise of his argument.

The obvious question that arises is why, given the stress Kant always makes on the absolutely unconditioned nature of moral freedom, he should feel able to make this claim. It would seem as if precisely the purity of the free will would make any connection to purposes immoral. Kant writes that, even speaking practically, we must consider ourselves. In other words, practical reason is a human faculty — where, as always for Kant, being human is defined in terms of a unity of a lower, sensible nature together with a higher, supersensible dimension.

Our sensibly conditioned will is not a different thing from our free will, but is the same faculty considered now as phenomenal psychology, now as noumenal activity. This must be the case if our actions in the phenomenal world are to be considered moral in any sense of the word.

But this sensibly conditioned will does require attention to be paid to consequences — to the object of our action. Free will may determine itself unconditionally through the mere form of the moral law, but it remains the faculty of will , that is the higher faculty of desire, and thus retains the essential link to purposes. The impossibility of achieving this end would make a nonsense of moral action, because it would in effect mean that free will was no longer will, that practical reason was no longer practical because it could not be said to act.

Kant is claiming that it is just part of the meaning of an action — even a purely and formally determined action, i. But the possibility of the summum bonum as the final purpose in nature is not at all obvious. Without the postulate of such a moral author — who, as we saw above, must have our free morality in mind as a final purpose, if anything — our free moral action could not be represented as possible. Moral action, precisely as both moral and as action , within itself assumes the existence of a God.

Of course, in acting morally we may not be conscious either of the summum bonum as final purpose, nor of the necessary postulation of God as moral author of the world — we are just doing what is right. Nevertheless, when that duty is fully understood, these necessary implications will be found within it. Theoretical philosophy must continue to operate within its legitimate grounds, treating so far as possible all of nature as intelligible in terms of mechanical cause and effect and requiring neither purpose nor creator.

This involves noting that the conception of God involved in the moral proof is and must be bound up with how things are cognizable by us. This of course continues the treatment of the intellectus ectypus begun in sect. Kant writes, As for objects that we have to think a priori either as consequences or as grounds in reference to our practical use of reason in conformity with duty, but that are transcendent for the theoretical use of reason: they are mere matters of faith. The summum bonum , God as moral author and the immortality of the soul, treated in the Critique of Practical Reason are all such objects of faith.

For Kant, this stress on faith keeps religion pure of the misunderstandings involved in, for example, fanaticism, demonology or idolatry sect. Obviously, questions can be raised about its validity. For example, whether the possibility of the final purpose is somehow necessarily linked to any moral action.

However, the typical objection — that the argument is insufficient to give any knowledge — is just irrelevant, since Kant is not interested in knowledge at this point. The problem of the unity of philosophy is the problem of how thought oriented towards knowledge theoretical reason can be a product of the same faculty as thought oriented towards moral duty practical reason. The problem of the unity of the objects of philosophy is the problem of how the ground of that which we know the supersensible ground of nature is the same as the ground of moral action the supersensible ground of that nature in which the summum bonum is possible — together with freedom within the subject.

Kant only makes some rather vague suggestions about how proof of these unities is to be established — but it is clear that he believes the faculty of judgment is the key. We will briefly look at the second of these problems. This amounts to the assumption that judgment will always be possible, even in cases like aesthetic judgment where no concept can be found.

This claim leads to two assertions. First, that the supersensible ground of beauty in nature is the same as the undetermined ground of nature as an object of science. Second, it is also capable of moral determination and thus also the same as the supersensible ground of moral nature.

Together, these two prove the unity of the supersensible objects of philosophy. Let us very briefly look at the grand problem Kant poses for himself in the Critique of Judgment. The following quotation contains the kernel. Kant is referring to the first Critique and especially to his solution to the Antinomies therein.

The solution there merely required that we recognize the distinction between appearances and things-in-themselves. But this solution required nothing further of the latter other than its mere negative definition: that it not be subject to the conditions of appearance. This purposiveness can only be accounted for if judgment assumes a supersensible that determines this purposiveness. It is no longer merely indeterminate. That is to say, judgment conceives of the supersensible as capable of receiving a determinate purpose, should there be good reasons for assuming there to be such a purpose.

It carries the summum bonum as its final purpose. Moreover, Judgment has, on the side of the subjective mind, made it conceivable to reason that its theoretical and practical employments are not only compatible that was proved already in the Antinomy concerning freedom but also capable of co-ordination towards moral purposes. Because, on the one hand, aesthetic judgment were found to be not fundamentally different from ordinary theoretical cognition of nature see A2 above , and on the other hand, aesthetic judgment has a deep similarity to moral judgment A5.

Thus, Kant has demonstrated that the physical and moral universes — and the philosophies and forms of thought that present them — are not only compatible, but unified. There are alternative, perfectly acceptable, translations of most of the following. Cambridge University Press, at the time of writing, is about half-way through publishing the complete works in English. For a treatment of various themes in Kant, please also see the introductions to the above editions.

Douglas Burnham Email: H. Burnham staffs. Immanuel Kant: Aesthetics Immanuel Kant is an 18th century German philosopher whose work initated dramatic changes in the fields of epistemology, metaphysics, ethics, aesthetics, and teleology.

Introduction a. Finally, of course, there is K c. The Sublime Overview: For Kant, the other basic type of aesthetic experience is the sublime. The absolutely large, however, is not the result of a comparison Now, of course, any object is measurable — even the size of the universe, no less a mountain on Earth. Kant writes, [W]e express ourselves entirely incorrectly when we call this or that object of nature sublime … for how can we call something by a term of approval if we apprehend it as in itself contrapurposive?

The former produces pleasure through sensation alone, the latter through various types of cognitions This taxonomy of fine art defines more precisely the issue for Kant. He writes, Genius is the talent natural endowment that gives the rule to art. Idealism, Morality and the Supersensible Overview: Let us return to the notion of beauty as tackled in sections A1 and A2.

He writes, Just as we must assume that objects of sense as appearances are ideal if we are to explain how we can determine their forms a priori, so we must presuppose an idealistic interpretation of purposiveness in judging the beautiful in nature and in art… sect. Kant writes that, even speaking practically, we must consider ourselves … as beings of the world and hence as beings connected with other things in the world; and those same moral laws enjoin us to direct our judging to those other things [regarded] either as purposes or as objects for which we ourselves are the final purpose sect.

Kant writes,.. Kant only makes some rather vague suggestions about how proof of these unities is to be established — but it is clear that he believes the faculty of judgment is the key We will briefly look at the second of these problems. References and Further Reading a. Aesthetics and Teleology. Indianapolis: Hackett, Critique of Judgment. Oxford: Clarendon, Critique of Practical Reason. Indianapolis: Hackett, b. Since this principle only regulates our cognition but is not constitutive of nature itself, this does not amount to assuming that nature really is the product of intelligent design, which according to Kant we are not justified in believing on theoretical grounds.

Rather, it amounts only to approaching nature in the practice of science as if it were designed to be understood by us.

We are justified in doing this because it enables us to discover empirical laws of nature. But it is only a regulative principle of reflecting judgment, not genuine theoretical knowledge, that nature is purposive in this way. Second, Kant thinks that aesthetic judgments about both beauty and sublimity involve a kind of purposiveness, and that the beauty of nature in particular suggests to us that nature is hospitable to our ends.

So beauty is not a property of objects, but a relation between their form and the way our cognitive faculties work.

Yet we make aesthetic judgments that claim intersubjective validity because we assume that there is a common sense that enables all human beings to communicate aesthetic feeling —, — Beautiful art is intentionally created to stimulate this universally communicable aesthetic pleasure, although it is effective only when it seems unintentional — Natural beauty, however, is unintentional: landscapes do not know how to stimulate the free play of our cognitive faculties, and they do not have the goal of giving us aesthetic pleasure.

In both cases, then, beautiful objects appear purposive to us because they give us aesthetic pleasure in the free play of our faculties, but they also do not appear purposive because they either do not or do not seem to do this intentionally.

Although it is only subjective, the purposiveness exhibited by natural beauty in particular may be interpreted as a sign that nature is hospitable to our moral interests Moreover, Kant also interprets the experience of sublimity in nature as involving purposiveness. Third, Kant argues that reflecting judgment enables us to regard living organisms as objectively purposive, but only as a regulative principle that compensates for our inability to fully understand them mechanistically, which reflects the limitations of our cognitive faculties rather than any intrinsic teleology in nature.

The parts of a watch are also possible only through their relation to the whole, but that is because the watch is designed and produced by some rational being. An organism, by contrast, produces and sustains itself, which is inexplicable to us unless we attribute to organisms purposes by analogy with human art — Specifically, we cannot understand how a whole can be the cause of its own parts because we depend on sensible intuition for the content of our thoughts and therefore must think the particular intuition first by subsuming it under the general a concept.

To see that this is just a limitation of the human, discursive intellect, imagine a being with an intuitive understanding whose thought does not depend, as ours does, on receiving sensory information passively, but rather creates the content of its thought in the act of thinking it. Such a divine being could understand how a whole can be the cause of its parts, since it could grasp a whole immediately without first thinking particulars and then combining them into a whole — Therefore, since we have a discursive intellect and cannot know how things would appear to a being with an intuitive intellect, and yet we can only think of organisms teleologically, which excludes mechanism, Kant now says that we must think of both mechanism and teleology only as regulative principles that we need to explain nature, rather than as constitutive principles that describe how nature is intrinsically constituted ff.

Fourth, Kant concludes the Critique of the Power of Judgment with a long appendix arguing that reflecting judgment supports morality by leading us to think about the final end of nature, which we can only understand in moral terms, and that conversely morality reinforces a teleological conception of nature. Once it is granted on theoretical grounds that we must understand certain parts of nature organisms teleologically, although only as a regulative principle of reflecting judgment, Kant says we may go further and regard the whole of nature as a teleological system — But we can regard the whole of nature as a teleological system only by employing the idea of God, again only regulatively, as its intelligent designer.

This involves attributing what Kant calls external purposiveness to nature — that is, attributing purposes to God in creating nature According to Kant, the final end of nature must be human beings, but only as moral beings , — This is because only human beings use reason to set and pursue ends, using the rest of nature as means to their ends — Moreover, Kant claims that human happiness cannot be the final end of nature, because as we have seen he holds that happiness is not unconditionally valuable — Rather, human life has value not because of what we passively enjoy, but only because of what we actively do We can be fully active and autonomous, however, only by acting morally, which implies that God created the world so that human beings could exercise moral autonomy.

Since we also need happiness, this too may be admitted as a conditioned and consequent end, so that reflecting judgment eventually leads us to the highest good Thus Kant argues that although theoretical and practical philosophy proceed from separate and irreducible starting points — self-consciousness as the highest principle for our cognition of nature, and the moral law as the basis for our knowledge of freedom — reflecting judgment unifies them into a single, teleological worldview that assigns preeminent value to human autonomy.

Life and works 2. Transcendental idealism 3. The transcendental deduction 4. Morality and freedom 5. The highest good and practical postulates 6. The unity of nature and freedom 7. Kant expresses this Enlightenment commitment to the sovereignty of reason in the Critique : Our age is the age of criticism, to which everything must submit.

Religion through its holiness and legislation through its majesty commonly seek to exempt themselves from it. But in this way they excite a just suspicion against themselves, and cannot lay claim to that unfeigned respect that reason grants only to that which has been able to withstand its free and public examination. Axi Enlightenment is about thinking for oneself rather than letting others think for you, according to What is Enlightenment?

As he explained in a February 21, letter to his friend and former student, Marcus Herz: In my dissertation I was content to explain the nature of intellectual representations in a merely negative way, namely, to state that they were not modifications of the soul brought about by the object.

However, I silently passed over the further question of how a representation that refers to an object without being in any way affected by it can be possible…. And if such intellectual representations depend on our inner activity, whence comes the agreement that they are supposed to have with objects — objects that are nevertheless not possibly produced thereby?

Kant characterizes this new constructivist view of experience in the Critique through an analogy with the revolution wrought by Copernicus in astronomy: Up to now it has been assumed that all our cognition must conform to the objects; but all attempts to find out something about them a priori through concepts that would extend our cognition have, on this presupposition, come to nothing.

Hence let us once try whether we do not get farther with the problems of metaphysics by assuming that the objects must conform to our cognition, which would agree better with the requested possibility of an a priori cognition of them, which is to establish something about objects before they are given to us.

This would be just like the first thoughts of Copernicus, who, when he did not make good progress in the explanation of the celestial motions if he assumed that the entire celestial host revolves around the observer, tried to see if he might not have greater success if he made the observer revolve and left the stars at rest.

Now in metaphysics we can try in a similar way regarding the intuition of objects. If intuition has to conform to the constitution of the objects, then I do not see how we can know anything of them a priori; but if the object as an object of the senses conforms to the constitution of our faculty of intuition, then I can very well represent this possibility to myself.

Yet because I cannot stop with these intuitions, if they are to become cognitions, but must refer them as representations to something as their object and determine this object through them, I can assume either that the concepts through which I bring about this determination also conform to the objects, and then I am once again in the same difficulty about how I could know anything about them a priori, or else I assume that the objects, or what is the same thing, the experience in which alone they can be cognized as given objects conforms to those concepts, in which case I immediately see an easier way out of the difficulty, since experience itself is a kind of cognition requiring the understanding, whose rule I have to presuppose in myself before any object is given to me, hence a priori, which rule is expressed in concepts a priori, to which all objects of experience must therefore necessarily conform, and with which they must agree.

Bxvi—xviii As this passage suggests, what Kant has changed in the Critique is primarily his view about the role and powers of the understanding, since he already held in the Inaugural Dissertation that sensibility contributes the forms of space and time — which he calls pure or a priori intuitions — to our cognition of the sensible world. Transcendental idealism Perhaps the central and most controversial thesis of the Critique of Pure Reason is that human beings experience only appearances, not things in themselves; and that space and time are only subjective forms of human intuition that would not subsist in themselves if one were to abstract from all subjective conditions of human intuition.

What may be the case with objects in themselves and abstracted from all this receptivity of our sensibility remains entirely unknown to us. We are acquainted with nothing except our way of perceiving them, which is peculiar to us, and which therefore does not necessarily pertain to every being, though to be sure it pertains to every human being. We are concerned solely with this.

Space and time are its pure forms, sensation in general its matter. We can cognize only the former a priori, i. The former adheres to our sensibility absolutely necessarily, whatever sort of sensations we may have; the latter can be very different. Space and time are not things in themselves, or determinations of things in themselves that would remain if one abstracted from all subjective conditions of human intuition.

Space and time are nothing other than the subjective forms of human sensible intuition. Most readers of Kant who have interpreted his transcendental idealism in this way have been — often very — critical of it, for reasons such as the following: First, at best Kant is walking a fine line in claiming on the one hand that we can have no knowledge about things in themselves, but on the other hand that we know that things in themselves exist, that they affect our senses, and that they are non-spatial and non-temporal.

The transcendental deduction The transcendental deduction is the central argument of the Critique of Pure Reason and one of the most complex and difficult texts in the history of philosophy. For they then are related necessarily and a priori to objects of experience, since only by means of them can any object of experience be thought at all.

Its highest principle is self-consciousness, on which our knowledge of the basic laws of nature is based. Given sensory data, our understanding constructs experience according to these a priori laws. Practical philosophy is about how the world ought to be ibid. Its highest principle is the moral law, from which we derive duties that command how we ought to act in specific situations. Kant also claims that reflection on our moral duties and our need for happiness leads to the thought of an ideal world, which he calls the highest good see section 6.

Given how the world is theoretical philosophy and how it ought to be practical philosophy , we aim to make the world better by constructing or realizing the highest good. This immediate consciousness of the moral law takes the following form: I have, for example, made it my maxim to increase my wealth by every safe means. Now I have a deposit in my hands, the owner of which has died and left no record of it.

This is, naturally, a case for my maxim. Now I want only to know whether that maxim could also hold as a universal practical law. I therefore apply the maxim to the present case and ask whether it could indeed take the form of a law, and consequently whether I could through my maxim at the same time give such a law as this: that everyone may deny a deposit which no one can prove has been made. I at once become aware that such a principle, as a law, would annihilate itself since it would bring it about that there would be no deposits at all.

The highest good and practical postulates Kant holds that reason unavoidably produces not only consciousness of the moral law but also the idea of a world in which there is both complete virtue and complete happiness, which he calls the highest good. The unity of nature and freedom This final section briefly discusses how Kant attempts to unify the theoretical and practical parts of his philosophical system in the Critique of the Power of Judgment.

Guyer and A. Wood eds. Its individual volumes are: Allison, H. Ameriks, K. Gregor, M. Guyer, P. Heath, P. Louden, R. Rauscher, F. Walford, D. Watkins, E. Wood, A. Young, J. Zweig, A. Other Primary Sources Jacobi, F. Fichte, J. Green ed. Locke, J. Nidditch ed. Reinhold, K. Ameriks ed. Sassen, B. Tetens, J. Secondary Literature Allais, L. Allison, H. Altman, M. Aquila, R. Beck, L. Robinson ed.

Beiser, F. Bennett, J. Bird, G. Engstrom, S. Friedman, M. Gardner, S. Grier, M. Ginsborg, H. Herman, C. Korsgaard, and T. Hill eds. Watkins ed. Henrich, D. Velkley ed. Hill, T. Jankowiak, T. Kanterian, E. Kemp Smith, N. Kitcher, P. Kleingeld, P. Korsgaard, C. Kuehn, M. Kukla, R. Langton, R. Laywine, A. Longuenesse, B. McFarland, J. Neiman, S. Paton, H. Prauss, G. In , Immanuel Kant published the Critique of Pure Reason , an enormous work and one of the most important on Western thought.

He attempted to explain how reason and experiences interact with thought and understanding. Kant focused on ethics, the philosophical study of moral actions. What is right is right and what is wrong is wrong; there is no grey area. Human beings are obligated to follow this imperative unconditionally if they are to claim to be moral. Though the Critique of Pure Reason received little attention at the time, Kant continued to refine his theories in a series of essays that comprised the Critique of Practical Reason and Critique of Judgement.

Kant continued to write on philosophy until shortly before his death. In his last years, he became embittered due to his loss of memory. He died in at age We strive for accuracy and fairness. By confining his conclusions to the world of experience, Kant is able to meet the threat of Humean skepticism and put natural science on a firm foundation. His moral philosophy is a philosophy of freedom.

Without human freedom, thought Kant, moral appraisal and moral responsibility would be impossible. Kant believes that if a person could not act otherwise, then his or her act can have no moral worth.

Further, he believes that every human being is endowed with a conscience that makes him or her aware that the moral law has authority over them. However, Kant also believes that the entire natural world is subject to a strict Newtonian principle of causality, implying that all of our physical actions are caused by prior events, not by our free wills. How, then, can freedom and morality be possible? The Critique of Pure Reason gives an account of theoretical reason and its limits.

Theoretical reason can understand the natural world through the categories of the understanding. Practical reason addresses questions of how the world ought to be and tells us our duty. It also leads humans to a concept of an ideal world, which it becomes our aim to create. However, the proper functioning of practical reason requires the existence of certain conditions, such as God, immortality of the soul, and, most importantly, free will.

Because none of these is contained within the categories of the understanding, theoretical reason can know nothing about them. However, argues Kant, because theoretical reason is also incapable of disproving their existence, we are justified in accepting their existence practically. According to Kant, ethics, like metaphysics, is a priori , meaning that our moral duty is determined independently of empirical considerations.

This moral principle is given by reason and states that we may act only in such a way that the maxim of our action, i. Those who act on non-universalizable maxims are caught in a kind of practical contradiction. In another formulation of the categorical imperative, Kant specifies that we must always respect humanity in ourselves and others by treating humans always as ends in themselves, and never merely as a means.

Instead, freedom implies morality, and morality implies freedom. Political activity is ultimately governed by moral principles based on human autonomy.



0コメント

  • 1000 / 1000